A recent article published in Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology examines various ways to understand loneliness as a part of human experience.
Valeria Motta, a doctoral researcher in philosophy at the University of Birmingham, suggests an approach that considers the lived experience of time, embodiment, and attention as fundamental dimensions of loneliness. She approaches the issue through the lens of phenomenological philosophy, or the study of in-depth lived experience.
āThere are good reasons to clarify the concept of loneliness. Loneliness has adverse effects on physical and mental health. It is a risk factor for morbidity and mortality in humans. Loneliness can be transientāa consequence of going through external circumstancesālike the loneliness that results from a bereavement, a change of city or social circles, or distance from friends, family or partners,ā Motta writes. Ā
āLoneliness can also be chronic distress without redeeming features. These observations have raised questions about whether loneliness should be characterized as pathology in its own right, and whether alleviating loneliness should be a key focus for clinicians.ā
In recent times, especially during the COVID-19 pandemic, there has been a surge of concern around the issue of loneliness. During the pandemic, young people have been especially vulnerable to loneliness. Some research suggests that loneliness may be more deadly than the COVID-19 virus.
Of course, even before COVID-19, loneliness has been studied and linked to a range of negative physical and mental health effects, including many āmental disorders.ā This has led some researchers to call loneliness a āpublic health threatā linked to the ideology of neoliberal capitalism.
The current paper reviews existing understandings of loneliness in different fields, such as psychology, sociology, and philosophy. Motta then suggests another understanding of loneliness from a philosophical perspective, examining the phenomenon in some of its phenomenological (experience-based) and social dimensions.
Motta outlines five different definitions of loneliness before presenting her own perspective.
The first definition focuses on āsocial needs,ā based on psychoanalytic and attachment theory, suggesting that people have an innate need for secure, nurturing, reassuring relationships. If these bonds are not formed in early life or disintegrate in later life, loneliness can result.
The second definition is based on ācognitive discrepancy.ā This approach focuses on cognitive processes more than social realities. Here, it is stated that people perceive themselves to be lonely. They may or may not possess actual quality social relationships, but there is an attitude or perception of loneliness. This can sometimes result from perceiving a discrepancy between a personās āwished forā quantity/quality of social relationships and what the person experiences.
An interesting finding in this research is that chronically lonely individuals have āvery high expectationsā for interpersonal relationships.
A third definition is called the āinteractionist approach.ā This definition combines ācharacter traitsā such as shyness with situational factors, such as hospitalization, income shifts, relocation, and cultural factors and expectations.
Fourth, there is a perspective where loneliness is āindicative of deficits in social relationships.ā This perspective views loneliness as a cluster of attitudes, cognitions, and behaviors. This includes social realities around lack of actual relationships, as well as the perception of loneliness.
Finally, there is an existential perspective on loneliness that relates it to a fundamental aspect of the human condition. In this understanding, loneliness relates to lifeās āultimate experiences,ā such as ābirth, death, change, tragedy.ā There can be a positive view here, where loneliness is linked to creativity and facing oneself and oneās life honestly.
Mottaās contribution to the existing definitions focuses more on phenomenological, or experience-based, dimensions of loneliness.
First, she emphasizes what she calls chronicity. Previous definitions of loneliness have made distinctions between, for example, (emotional) state and (character) trait-based loneliness, as well as transient and chronic loneliness.
Motta argues, however, that there is much room for improvement in this area. She suggests a few directions that a ālived experienceā based understanding of loneliness could pursue, such as: whether loneliness āfeels longerā than when people feel socially connected, how states of loneliness affect our memories of the past, as well as how feeling lonely affects our view of the future. All these facets, and more, could give researchers a clearer understanding of loneliness and how to treat it.
Mottaās second dimension is related to attention, or what she calls āattentional space.ā This relates to three kinds of loneliness: intimate, relational, and collective. Intimate loneliness is concerned with a personās inner circle of relationships, usually no more than around five people. This can include a spouse/significant other/life partner. People who have a significant other are less likely to experience intimate loneliness.
The second kind of loneliness is relational (or social) loneliness. This is a larger circle of social support that can include family, friends, colleagues, and more as part of a āsympathy group.ā The number of people here is often around 15-50. In middle age and older adults, āfrequent contact with family and friends is the best (negative) predictor of relational loneliness.ā
The third kind of loneliness for Motta is collective loneliness. This is oneās social system at a larger and more abstract level, such as political party, nation, or another kind of group (like fans of sports teams). The number here is typically 150+ people. Dr. Motta describes this group as not offering āstrong ties,ā but as offering āinformationā and ālow-cost support.ā Middle-aged and older adults who belong to more voluntary groups are less likely to experience loneliness, as an example.
Ultimately, Motta argues that further research into the lived experience of loneliness can clarify these dimensions and their boundaries, giving us a better idea of how to approach the treatment of loneliness. Of course, she does note that people can feel an āabsenceā or loneliness even in the presence of friends, family, and more, which calls into question using this framework as a perfectly accurate understanding of loneliness.
The final dimension discussed is the body, specifically the lived body, which is different from the physiological body according to phenomenological philosophy. The lived body grounds our perspective on the world. It is the ground of experience rather than a āthingā we pay attention to as an external object.
Motta argues that loneliness should also be understood in terms of the lived body and its environmental possibilities. For example:
āA way to illustrate this is to think that a person in solitary confinement has very different possibilities for interaction with the environment from someone who is out in nature or in a big city and that this alters their experience. Incarceration is a particularly good example that illustrates not only the effects of immobility but also the extent to which the regimentation of time and the phenomenology of waiting can become different sorts of psychic torture.ā
Motta concludes:
āPotential areas for research that have already been identified are the temporality of loneliness and the role of attention and perception in the experience of loneliness. I have argued that we need definitions of loneliness that address disturbances (e.g., absences) or experiential abnormalities (e.g., embodied experiences) in subjective structure. Exploring the issues raised here would have implications for our terminology and our future research on types of loneliness. These would, in turn, allow for the design of new treatments and interventions.ā
****
Motta, V. (2021). Key concept: Loneliness. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 28(1), 71-81. (Link)